In “On the Very Idea of a Conceptual Scheme,” Davidson attacks the scheme/content division by way of questioning conceptual relativism.  That is, he points out that conceptual relativism is a “heady” notion wrought by an underlying paradox: “different points of view make sense, but only if there is a common coordinate system on which to plot them; yet the existence of a common system bellies the claim of dramatic incomparability.”  The goal of his analysis is to tease out in what sense this paradox is fatal versus in what sense it is just interesting, and he does this mainly by ‘equating’ languages and conceptual schemes.  That is, as a way of approaching the problem, at least as a first approximation, Davidson turns the problem of relative conceptual schemes into a question of translatability among languages, with partial failure versus complete failure dictating the sense in which schemes can be relative, or if even “relativity” can be said of them at all.[1]  In the final analysis, his conclusion is pragmatic and agnostic, for he finds “no intelligible basis on which it can be said that schemes are different,” but “neither can we intelligibly say that they are one”.  As such, we should give up the very idea of the scheme/content division in order to “reestablish unmediated touch with the familiar objects’” of daily life that makes our “sentences and opinions true or false.”

Now the anus likes unmediated touch with familiar objects, and it’s never been fond of “paradigms” and “schemes,” except in a fast and loose approximation that dissolves itself on a closer look.  Thus the anus likes seeing Kuhn—and by extension Rorty, though he of course is not mentioned here—taken to task for somehow pointing out not just that but also how notions, ostensibly incommensurable, are in principle incommensurable but in practice comparable using independent but unacknowledged reference points based on something, on some kind of common ground, even if “a view from nowhere” or ‘permanent neutral framework is deemed impossible.  So the anus thinks Davidson is right to put some meat on the bones of the all too often merely formal inconsistency of conceptual relativists and schemers, but it wonders how his analysis fares with perhaps the greatest conceptual schemer of all, Kant.  Specifically, does Davidson’s analysis of, and therefore agnostic conclusion about, the scheme/content distinction apply to Kant’s transcendental account of the subsumption of intuitions (the content) under the concepts of the understanding (the scheme) in the constitution of experience?  In another essay, “The Myth of the Subjective,” he indicates that it does, but that application bears examining.

On first blush, it seems unlikely that the argument against conceptual schemes via the paradox of conceptual relativism will apply very well to Kant because Kant was in no way a conceptual relativist.  In fact, his transcendental analysis is in no small part a response to conceptual relativism, and in his mind the only antidote for it.  But really this first blush conceals a hidden intent as much as it reveals a denial, for it would apply on the one hand to Kant in that for him, though unstated explicitly, the “conceptual scheme” is all one—that is, the constituting activities of the mind are universal to all rational creatures; but on the other hand but it would not apply in the sense that for him, conceptual scheme itself is decidable via the problem of translation—that is, all experience, for everyone, is lawful and orderly in the same sense, therefore  all empirical claims are in the end ‘translatable’ according to the same rules, i.e. in other words they are for all intents and purposes completely translatable into transcendental rules.  So it’s clear that for Kant there is a sense in which there is a universal, single conceptual scheme, but it remains unclear if the consequences of the dual arguments from partial or complete failure of translation would apply to him because for Kant all relative empirical claims are completely ‘translatable’ into a transcendental grounding, as it were—or to put the matter more precisely, they are interchangeable and/or arbitratable against a neutral matrix of common ground, through a single set of rules, and that common ground is constituted experience.  So the question of whether Davidson’s attack on this “third dogma” of empiricism applies to Kant boils down to the question of experience, and more specifically to how the “scheme/content” distinction in Kant relates to that experience.

Now Davidson distinguishes two ways in which a conceptual scheme relates to experience: it can organize experience or it can fit experience, with the difference being systemizing and dividing up “the stream of experience” for the former versus predicting and accounting for particulars or events against the “tribunal of experience” for the later.  He goes on to distinguish within organizing experience between organizing reality (the world, nature) and organizing things within experience (as surface irritations, sense data, etc.), then he rejects as problematic both senses of organize and the single sense of fit.  The details of his argument seem weak in some respects, especially regarding organizing experience, but their force can be granted without affecting an underlying point critical to his argument, or the argument here.  In both cases, Davidson is presuming that there is such a thing as experience to be organized or fitted in the first place.  That is, in his analysis of how the scheme applies to contents given in experience, either as a single entity like “the world” or a plurality of objects like “objects in the world,” experience itself, in some sense, is taken for granted as always already there to be fitted or organized.  In neither case does he go any distance to making the possibility of experience as such problematic, and this failure bears directly on the applicability of his analysis to Kant because that is precisely what Kant did.   His version of the “scheme/content” distinction works at that transcendental level.  In other words, Kant was concerned with the possibility of experience as such, not per se with the organization or fitting of experience as first presumed, and this casts serious doubt on the applicability of Davidson’s analysis to Kant.

To put the matter more directly in the context of Davidson’s argument, Kant never argued that the categories (read “conceptual scheme”) apply to (read “organize” or “fit”) experience per se without simultaneously saying that the application of the categories to intuition is experience itself—and Davidson misses this duality of application/constitution in his exploration of the scheme/content duality.  As Kant states repeatedly, the ‘application’ of the categories ‘to’ intuition anticipates not just the organization of a given experience but rather represents “the form of possible experience in general,” such that “the principles of the pure understanding are nothing more than the principles apriori of the possibility of experience” itself.  Or to put it in terms of Davidson’s closet illustration, the “conceptual scheme” for Kant doesn’t organize the closet taken as such, or even the closet taken as full of objects, as much as it makes possible the experience of a closet with objects in it that is as such organizable or fittable at all—the “conceptual scheme,” as it were, in making coherent experience possible, precedes the application of a conceptual scheme in Davidson’s more restricted sense of application to actual experience.  This making possible a closet with contents to be organized (in Davidson’s more limited senses) is clear in Kant’s summary statement, again repeated several times in the Critique as its principle conclusion: “the conditions of the possibility of experience in general are likewise the conditions of the possibility of objects of experience”.  In this transcendental respect, Davidson’s arguments against scheme and content organizing or fitting experience overlooks the constitutive role Kant gives his “conceptual scheme,” and this omission renders his “On the very idea” analysis of the scheme/content dogma inapplicable to Kant without further argumentation.   In other words, Davidson may have compelling objections to a “third dogma” of empiricism; it’s just that the empiricism of application is not Kant’s empirical realism subtended by a transcendental idealism.[2]

But this picture is incomplete, for in one respect Davidson’s argument both has a deeper force than so far indicated, even as in that respect it actually loses all of its force as it might apply to any transcendentalist like Kant.  That is, under the stipulation that psychological nominalism is true, Davidson’s rejection of the scheme/content distinction via the route of failure or translatability is convincing: it would apply, for instance, to Sellars’ attempt to re-establish the distinction within psychological nominalism after purging it of the Myth of the Given.  But since this stipulation is in fact false, Davidson’s argument loses all force against anyone who proposes, like Kant, that what is inherent to a so-called “conceptual scheme” is active in pre-linguistic experience—an experience rich in cognition that gets taken up and magnified into more directly “conceptual” schemes inherent ‘in’ language after the fact.   Current candidates for this pre-linguistic ‘scheme’ include many, if not most, of Kant’s categories, though to be sure not in the epistemological function that Kant intended them.  Causality and dependence, quantity, negation, inherence and subsistence—these cognitions, and many others, in their non-epistemological purposing, have been empirically demonstrated not just in pre-linguistic infants but also in non-linguistic primates.  As such, they ‘constitute’ experience in a sense prior to any conceptual scheme that can be equated, in any sense, with language.   In Kant’s terms, they are transcendental, at least with respect to language (and hence to the question of translation) because they are inherent to experience prior to its acquisition, even if by other arguments they can’t play the epistemologically constitutive role Kant assigns to them in determining the possibility of synthetic apriori judgments.  In any case, they still ‘structure’ pre-linguistic experience in that they are the organization of that experience.   At the end of the day, Davidson’s arguments against the scheme/content dogma via arguments against conceptual relativism via the problems of translatability don’t apply to Kant because first, they only apply conclusively to psychological nominalists, and Kant is no psychological nominalist; and second, “conceptually schematic” elements like causality, negation, object permanence, quantity, etc. are empirically demonstrable in pre- and non-linguistic subjects, therefore the issue of translatability is completely impotent to arbitrate their relationship to experience when experience is taken problematically, whether that relationship be in an organizing or fitting capacity.  In short, the third dogma is specific to an empiricism that no more applies to Kant than it does to current empirical knowledge of what non-linguistic experience is actually like, i.e. to some forms of modern empiricism or transcendentalism.  As such, Davidson’s rejection of the scheme/content distinction has no independent force outside a rather limited context of distinctions and arguments anal-lytic philosophers are so fond of making (which really is of no concern to anyone else).[3]

As a thorough pragmatist, the anus applauds Davidson’s rejection of the very dilemma of an “interpreted” versus an “uninterpreted” reality in a return to the “unmediated touch” of familiar things, but he fails to see how it applies to an empiricism that conceives experience without the conceptual hobble-crutch that is psychological nominalism.   Like Davidson, the anus prefers its experience neat, even if it is forced to drink from a different cup in a toast to a thinker like Kant.

_____________________________________________

 

[1] It remains unclear in just what sense conceptual schemes and language are ‘equated’ beyond the stipulation that “associates having a language with having a conceptual scheme,” and presumably vice versa.  The anus happens to think this doctrine is problematic, though not necessarily fatally so, but the sense in which it is will not be raised yet and the stipulation will be granted on its face.  Only mention will be made that it seems possible that important elements of a “conceptual scheme” could be pre-linguistic, and that language magnifies this pre-linguistic cognition through the action of other language-specific cognitive mechanisms.  This possibility would only seem impossible to a psychological nominalist, but that reluctance is neither here nor there because psychological nominalism is false.  The details of this pre-linguistic cognition have been explored in extensive empirical research on primates, infants, and young children, as well as the development of these forms in language acquisition and use during later development.  This idea will be taken up shortly as it pertains to Davidson’s point about scheme and content.

 

[2] This is not to say that Davidson’s argument couldn’t be extended to encompass a transcendental argument, but how it fails to do so as currently stated is developed next.

 

[3] Another  way to contextualize the limits of Davidson’s critique: the criterion of translatability would apply only to an empiricism under which psychological nominalism is true, but since psychological nominalism is in fact false, his critique has little real independent applicability to empiricism as such, much less any force for exposing a “third dogma” within it.

Leave a Reply

Please log in using one of these methods to post your comment:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Google photo

You are commenting using your Google account. Log Out /  Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s